ArtsAutosBooksBusinessEducationEntertainmentFamilyFashionFoodGamesGenderHealthHolidaysHomeHubPagesPersonal FinancePetsPoliticsReligionSportsTechnologyTravel

Scepticism of the Ancient Greek Philosophers

Updated on December 12, 2009

 

The sceptical contention is that we cannot know anything at all, not even whether the sceptical contention itself is true. This doctrine led the ancient sceptics to suspend judgement on many issues, including whether objects really were the way they appeared to be, and, whether there were such things truth and falsity, and even whether there were actions that were morally right or wrong. It is the latter subject I would like to take issue with here. The sceptics argue that it is reasonable to suspend judgement over whether any action is either a morally good or a morally bad action because we cannot know which actions are good or bad. But I disagree with this proposition.  Here, I will offer a criticism of the sceptical argument for this position and provide my own argument for the common-sense belief that there are morally good and bad actions.

 

The sceptics developed a system of ten modes that helped illustrate the various ways in which we cannot know anything at all. Since the sceptics concluded that nothing at all could be known, it made sense to suspend judgement on matters that were of an uncertain nature. Since everything was of an uncertain nature, the sceptics suspended judgement over everything. One significant topic the sceptics chose to suspend judgment over was whether there could be any such thing as a morally right or wrong action. The sceptics argued that because there was no agreement among people as to what constituted a morally good action, it followed that there simply was no such thing as a morally right or wrong action (p. 295). For example, the sceptics argued that some cultures considered it morally acceptable for a father to have sexual intercourse with his daughter; however, other cultures considered such a practice morally despicable (p. 290). That the same practice was held to be good by some cultures and bad by others suggested that there was no objective right or wrong action; thus, we ought to suspend judgement in these matters.

 

To state the sceptical position concerning the suspension of judgement over right and wrong actions, we can construct the following argument: 1) good and bad are human constructs, so nothing is either good or bad by nature; 2) if it were true that good and bad were good and bad by nature, the same things would have to be good or bad for everyone; however, 3) there is nothing that is good or bad for everyone; therefore, 4) there is nothing good or bad by nature (p .295).

 

This argument has at least two problems: one is its logical structure; second, are the logical consequences that follow from the conclusion. First, we will address the problems with its logical structure. Upon examination of the premises and the conclusion, we will notice that premise #1 is virtually identical to the conclusion. That is, premise #1 says, in part, ‘…nothing is either good or bad by nature.’ Yet, this is the very same statement we arrive at in our conclusion. Thus, this argument is circular, and as such, we ought to dismiss it as an illegitimate attempt to persuade us of the sceptical doctrine.

 

In response to this accusation levelled against this argument, the sceptics would likely remove the first premise, since it is question begging, and begin the argument anew at premise #2. Thus the argument would then become: 1) if it were true that good and bad were good and bad by nature, the same things would have to be good or bad for everyone; however, 3) there is nothing that is good or bad for everyone; therefore, 4) there is nothing good or bad by nature. This restructuring of the argument eliminates the problem of circularity. However, as noted above, there is still a second problem with this argument.

 

The second problem with this argument is the consequences that inevitably follow from the conclusion. While disagreeing with a conclusion is not a sign of a bad argument, this conclusion does seem counter-intuitive for several reasons. If we accept the conclusion that there is nothing good or bad by nature, then it would seem that no one could ever do anything wrong. But this is surely unacceptable. If this were the case, we could never be justified in punishing someone for his or her actions, because there would be no such thing as a good or bad action. Furthermore, it would appear that the sceptics could not even allow that a member of a community could ever do right or wrong according to the standards of his or her community, because, as the sceptics conclude, there is nothing good or bad by nature. In other words, you could not do right or wrong, even when the laws and customs of your own community forbid you from committing such acts. Therefore, it seems laws would be completely arbitrary.

 

If, however, we are not prepared to accept the sceptical conclusion and the consequences that follow, we must see if we can construct an opposing argument to counter the sceptical conclusion. I would argue that if there is nothing good or bad by nature, then it would follow that no one could ever do anything wrong. But, if no one could ever do anything wrong, this would render people infallible. But we know that people are fallible; hence, it must be the case that good and bad do exist. Here is an argument from James Rachels that states this position quite succinctly: 1) if there is no such thing as a good or bad action, then we are infallible; but, 2) we are not infallible; therefore, 3) good and bad do exist (p. 35).

 

It would seem that the force of this new argument rests in our acceptance of premise #2: we are not infallible. We undoubtedly have many good reasons to think that humans are fallible. To argue this point seems almost unnecessary. However, there is much at stake if we can strengthen our argument. Therefore, I will offer an attempt to support our premise. To be fallible is to be capable of making a mistake, and we all make mistakes from time to time. We can make errors in our speech by saying a wrong word here or there. We can, and often do, make simple mistakes in arithmetic when adding or subtracting numbers in our head. We can make a mistake in identifying someone as a person we thought we knew, etc. We could go on a great deal to prove this statement further, but I think that will not be necessary. Most would willingly agree that it is obvious that humans are indeed capable of making mistakes, and are therefore, fallible; to argue otherwise seems pointless. Hence, if we accept that humans are not infallible, our conclusion follows that good and bad do exist.

 

Bibliography

 

Hellenistic Philosophy: Introductory Readings. 2nd ed. Eds. Brad Inwood and L.P. Gerson, (Hackett, 1997).

 

James Rachels, The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 4th ed. (McGraw-Hill, 2003).

 

 

 

 

 

working

This website uses cookies

As a user in the EEA, your approval is needed on a few things. To provide a better website experience, hubpages.com uses cookies (and other similar technologies) and may collect, process, and share personal data. Please choose which areas of our service you consent to our doing so.

For more information on managing or withdrawing consents and how we handle data, visit our Privacy Policy at: https://corp.maven.io/privacy-policy

Show Details
Necessary
HubPages Device IDThis is used to identify particular browsers or devices when the access the service, and is used for security reasons.
LoginThis is necessary to sign in to the HubPages Service.
Google RecaptchaThis is used to prevent bots and spam. (Privacy Policy)
AkismetThis is used to detect comment spam. (Privacy Policy)
HubPages Google AnalyticsThis is used to provide data on traffic to our website, all personally identifyable data is anonymized. (Privacy Policy)
HubPages Traffic PixelThis is used to collect data on traffic to articles and other pages on our site. Unless you are signed in to a HubPages account, all personally identifiable information is anonymized.
Amazon Web ServicesThis is a cloud services platform that we used to host our service. (Privacy Policy)
CloudflareThis is a cloud CDN service that we use to efficiently deliver files required for our service to operate such as javascript, cascading style sheets, images, and videos. (Privacy Policy)
Google Hosted LibrariesJavascript software libraries such as jQuery are loaded at endpoints on the googleapis.com or gstatic.com domains, for performance and efficiency reasons. (Privacy Policy)
Features
Google Custom SearchThis is feature allows you to search the site. (Privacy Policy)
Google MapsSome articles have Google Maps embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
Google ChartsThis is used to display charts and graphs on articles and the author center. (Privacy Policy)
Google AdSense Host APIThis service allows you to sign up for or associate a Google AdSense account with HubPages, so that you can earn money from ads on your articles. No data is shared unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
Google YouTubeSome articles have YouTube videos embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
VimeoSome articles have Vimeo videos embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
PaypalThis is used for a registered author who enrolls in the HubPages Earnings program and requests to be paid via PayPal. No data is shared with Paypal unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
Facebook LoginYou can use this to streamline signing up for, or signing in to your Hubpages account. No data is shared with Facebook unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
MavenThis supports the Maven widget and search functionality. (Privacy Policy)
Marketing
Google AdSenseThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Google DoubleClickGoogle provides ad serving technology and runs an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Index ExchangeThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
SovrnThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Facebook AdsThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Amazon Unified Ad MarketplaceThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
AppNexusThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
OpenxThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Rubicon ProjectThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
TripleLiftThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Say MediaWe partner with Say Media to deliver ad campaigns on our sites. (Privacy Policy)
Remarketing PixelsWe may use remarketing pixels from advertising networks such as Google AdWords, Bing Ads, and Facebook in order to advertise the HubPages Service to people that have visited our sites.
Conversion Tracking PixelsWe may use conversion tracking pixels from advertising networks such as Google AdWords, Bing Ads, and Facebook in order to identify when an advertisement has successfully resulted in the desired action, such as signing up for the HubPages Service or publishing an article on the HubPages Service.
Statistics
Author Google AnalyticsThis is used to provide traffic data and reports to the authors of articles on the HubPages Service. (Privacy Policy)
ComscoreComScore is a media measurement and analytics company providing marketing data and analytics to enterprises, media and advertising agencies, and publishers. Non-consent will result in ComScore only processing obfuscated personal data. (Privacy Policy)
Amazon Tracking PixelSome articles display amazon products as part of the Amazon Affiliate program, this pixel provides traffic statistics for those products (Privacy Policy)
ClickscoThis is a data management platform studying reader behavior (Privacy Policy)