ArtsAutosBooksBusinessEducationEntertainmentFamilyFashionFoodGamesGenderHealthHolidaysHomeHubPagesPersonal FinancePetsPoliticsReligionSportsTechnologyTravel

Epicurus: Gods and Death - To Be or Not To Be?

Updated on February 17, 2011
japtaker profile image

Justin Aptaker graduated summa cum laude from the University of Tennessee, earning a BA in psychology and a minor in religious studies.

To be, or not to be?
To be, or not to be? | Source

The renowned philosopher of ancient Greece, Epicurus, in his Letter to Menoeceus, says that "death is nothing to us, and to know this makes a mortal life happy". The first half of this statement is clarified by Epicurus' Principal Doctrine II: "Death is nothing to us, because a body that has been dispersed into elements experiences no sensations, and the absence of sensation is nothing to us." Lucretius, a Roman philosopher of Epicurean persuasion, further explains, "One who no longer is cannot suffer" (De Rerum Natura III.867). I won't directly argue with the Epicurean belief that death is eternal nonexistence, except to say that no human has ever known with certainty what death entails. My argument is mainly against the wording of the the second clause, which makes it seem that a firmly held belief that death is nothingness universally and necessarily makes a life happy. If one's life is weighed down with fears of future punishments after death, or with a sense that life itself is an imprisonment to arbitrary divine laws, a new-found belief in annihilation could certainly make life happier. But for the rest of us, it wouldn't seem that the idea of nonexistence would make for a life with any additional happiness.

Epicurus and Lucretius went to considerable length in their attempts to rid their hearers of fearsome superstitions concerning the gods, with the admirable hope of releasing them from the existential anxiety necessarily born of such superstitions. Once a person comes to realize that their death will bring about a complete end of consciousness, there is no reason to fear that punishment from the gods may await them beyond the grave. Once convinced that the gods can not punish the dead, however, one might naturally revert to to common fear that the gods punish the living. Epicurus has a ready counter to that fear as well. Speaking of the gods, he states, "A blessed and imperishable being neither has trouble itself nor does it cause trouble for anyone else. . ." (Principal Doctrine I). By portraying the gods as serene beings who do not involve themselves with human affairs, Epicureanism freed its believers from the fear that their lives and fortunes are at the mercy of selfish and arbitrary deities.

Epicurus' value system considers pleasure to be "the greatest good" (Letter to Menoeceus, 133). Pleasure, in the sense that Epicurus meant it, referred simply to an absence of physical and mental suffering (Letter to Menoeceus, 128). Fear, being one of the most terrible forms of mental suffering, should have no place in one's life. In this light, the belief that death is nothingness is easily mistaken for an essential link to the good life, as it eradicates the superstitious terror of punishment after death. But this belief is not a universal prescription for happiness. For example, there may be numerous people who don't believe that death is nothingness, but nonetheless have no fear of gods or divine punishment. To find such people, one need only find someone with the Epicurean notion of the gods. Since such gods--far removed from human concerns--cause no trouble for anyone, they must refrain from harming not only the living, but also the dead. Any person who believes in such gods as those of Epicurus will feel no fear that the gods will torment them after death, so this fear can be removed without believing death is nonexistence.

At this point someone might put forth a very reasonable argument on behalf of Epicurus, going something like this: "I say with Epicurus that pleasure is the greatest good, and that pleasure is nothing but the absence of pain. It follows that perfect happiness comes only by believing death to be nothing. If death is nothing--the absence of sensation--as we say, then it involves absolute absence of pain, both in mind and in body. Thus, death is more complete a removal of all pain than we can even conceive of while still living. Since life offers nothing greater than freedom from pain, and death removes pain as life never could, death offers the greatest good to the highest degree possible. A person who knows these things will be made supremely happy in life, by knowing that this perfect blessedness is impossible for any person to miss out on!"

In the face of such an argument, it seems good to look closely at the ideas Epicurus has about both pleasure and goodness. His third principal doctrine states, "Pleasure reaches its maximum limit at the removal of all sources of pain." Again, he says that "when we no longer feel pain, we have all the pleasure we need" (Letter to Menoeceus, 128). Now, the dead no longer feel pain of any sort. The quintessential source of pain--consciousness--has been thoroughly removed. Therefore, only the dead experience pleasure in its highest state. This, of course, sounds absurd. If a person does not exist, they can not be said to experience anything, and we don't call anything that isn't experienced pleasurable.

Again, Epicurus calls pleasure "the greatest good" (Letter to Menoeceus, 133). In order for anything to be called good, it must be considered good in relation to something. A good car, for example, is not good by some quality of goodness in itself, but is considered good only in its usefulness to people. Water, itself neither good nor bad, is bad for the lungs, but good for trees. The absence of pain is good for sentient creatures. If nothing had ever existed, the idea of good would be impossible, because good must be good with respect to something. And so, in relation to people who exist, a greatest good might truly exist. No good can exist, however, in relation to dead people, if one who dies "no longer is" (Lucretius, De Rerum Natura III.867). For if the dead are nothing, nothing can be good in relation to them, as every good must be good in relation to something.

Next, Epicurus says that this greatest good is "easily supplied to absolute fullness, while pain, the greatest evil, lasts only a moment when intense and is easily tolerated when prolonged" (Letter to Menoeceus, 133). So human life can become such that its pain is scarcely perceptible within the abundance of this good. Epicurus doesn't even think it impossible for one to "live like a god among men" (Letter to Menoeceus, Conclusion). For Lucretius, the Epicurean idea of what it means to live like a god is as follows: "For it is essential to the very nature of deity that it should enjoy immortal existence in utter tranquility . . . free from all pain and peril" (Lucretius, De Rerum Natura II.645-648). If we take Epicurus literally when he speaks of humans living like gods, it follows that certain people may live utterly free of pain and suffering, and do so forever. If Epicurus isn't one to be taken literally, we should at least suppose that he felt philosophically justified in saying that a human life can become like a god's life. He must have thought it possible for the good in a human life to so outweigh the bad that we may consider the bad to be completely negated, otherwise he would allow that the lives of deities have pains, thus contradicting himself.

If human life truly has the capacity to ascend to heights at which it is not blasphemous (or just nonsensical) to liken it to divine life, and divine life enjoys the utter fullness of the greatest good for humans, then humans should strive to be like the gods. This would be striving to obtain in full what is good with respect to people, which is freedom from pain. In John Godwin's introduction to the Penguin Classics 1994 publication of Lucretius' On the Nature of the Universe, the gods are said to be "paradigms of a happiness that we ourselves could obtain, the role models of that Epicurean serenity which is the goal of . . . the philosophical system" (pp xvi-xvii). One passage that Godwin cites to support this claim states that "[if you don't reject notions] unworthy of the gods and foreign to their tranquility, then the holy beings whom you thus diminish will often do you real harm" (Lucretius, De Rerum Natura VI.69-71). Lucretius goes on to explain that this harm is not caused--as is expected by the holder of false, fearful conceptions of gods--by angry deities exacting revenge. The harm results from such a one's own fearfulness, which prevents them from receiving the true "images" of the gods. A bad life is likely to be the result. (De Rerum Natura VI.71-80). So the gods actually do affect us a great deal, but passively. The effect they have on us is due to our conception of them. If we contemplate them as they are, we may be blessed by becoming more like them in their serene and untroubled natures.

By considering the writings of Epicurus and Lucretius, the following three points are established. First, that the gods live utterly free of pain, which is the fullness of mankind's greatest good. So the clearest way for a human to reach the highest possible degree of human good is to live like the gods, if that is possible. Second, that the dead are nothing, as they do not exist at all. So without life, there is utterly no good with respect to humans. Third, that humans may obtain the good to the degree that they can be said to live like gods, which means that their fullness of good is so complete as to make considerations of any bad in their lives negligible. So with life, good is available humans in utter fullness. Without life, no good is possible for people at all. So life is useful and necessary for humans to obtain any and all good, which means that life is good in relation to our pursuit and acquisition of good. And by extension, life is good in relation to humans.

There are two means by which all suffering may depart from a life: either by death or by becoming like a god. Of these, only becoming godlike provides the good, while death provides nothing. Epicurus tells Menoeceus that he has the ability, if he properly heeds Epicurus, to live like a god (Letter to Menoeceus, Conclusion). Saying this, he reveals his own conviction (perhaps subconscious), that to live like a god is desirable and worth the effort involved in reaching that condition. On the other hand, Epicurus reveals a belief that death is not desirable or good. He says, "One who is wise neither renounces life nor fears not living" and "it's desirable to live" (Letter to Menoeceus, 126). So he maintains that death is not to be feared, as it involves no suffering. But life being good, and death being nothing, one should never choose death over life, as that is a bad trade. But to live like a god is supremely good, as that is the final reward Epicurus promises the one who would diligently practice his teaching (Letter to Menoeceus, Conclusion).

With something perhaps like a Freudian slip, Epicurus has shown us what really lies behind all his rhetoric. He says that the faithful practice of his philosophy will enable one to live like a god. Gods live free of pain, but they also live without end. Although he didn't claim that his philosophy offers immortality, perhaps his promise here of a godlike life tells us that he wishes his philosophy provided immortality. Both by refusing to "renounce life", and by honoring the godlike life, he affirms his own feelings that nothingness offers nothing, whereas life offers good, and the highest good is found in conjunction with endless life. So death is a loss both of the good that is and the greater good that can be imagined. While we can refuse to fear or lament that fact, the fact in itself doesn't seem like the surest cause for happiness.

Poll: What do you believe about death?

See results
  • If you enjoyed my writing in this article, please take a moment to look at some of my short poems: click here.

working

This website uses cookies

As a user in the EEA, your approval is needed on a few things. To provide a better website experience, hubpages.com uses cookies (and other similar technologies) and may collect, process, and share personal data. Please choose which areas of our service you consent to our doing so.

For more information on managing or withdrawing consents and how we handle data, visit our Privacy Policy at: https://corp.maven.io/privacy-policy

Show Details
Necessary
HubPages Device IDThis is used to identify particular browsers or devices when the access the service, and is used for security reasons.
LoginThis is necessary to sign in to the HubPages Service.
Google RecaptchaThis is used to prevent bots and spam. (Privacy Policy)
AkismetThis is used to detect comment spam. (Privacy Policy)
HubPages Google AnalyticsThis is used to provide data on traffic to our website, all personally identifyable data is anonymized. (Privacy Policy)
HubPages Traffic PixelThis is used to collect data on traffic to articles and other pages on our site. Unless you are signed in to a HubPages account, all personally identifiable information is anonymized.
Amazon Web ServicesThis is a cloud services platform that we used to host our service. (Privacy Policy)
CloudflareThis is a cloud CDN service that we use to efficiently deliver files required for our service to operate such as javascript, cascading style sheets, images, and videos. (Privacy Policy)
Google Hosted LibrariesJavascript software libraries such as jQuery are loaded at endpoints on the googleapis.com or gstatic.com domains, for performance and efficiency reasons. (Privacy Policy)
Features
Google Custom SearchThis is feature allows you to search the site. (Privacy Policy)
Google MapsSome articles have Google Maps embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
Google ChartsThis is used to display charts and graphs on articles and the author center. (Privacy Policy)
Google AdSense Host APIThis service allows you to sign up for or associate a Google AdSense account with HubPages, so that you can earn money from ads on your articles. No data is shared unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
Google YouTubeSome articles have YouTube videos embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
VimeoSome articles have Vimeo videos embedded in them. (Privacy Policy)
PaypalThis is used for a registered author who enrolls in the HubPages Earnings program and requests to be paid via PayPal. No data is shared with Paypal unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
Facebook LoginYou can use this to streamline signing up for, or signing in to your Hubpages account. No data is shared with Facebook unless you engage with this feature. (Privacy Policy)
MavenThis supports the Maven widget and search functionality. (Privacy Policy)
Marketing
Google AdSenseThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Google DoubleClickGoogle provides ad serving technology and runs an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Index ExchangeThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
SovrnThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Facebook AdsThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Amazon Unified Ad MarketplaceThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
AppNexusThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
OpenxThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Rubicon ProjectThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
TripleLiftThis is an ad network. (Privacy Policy)
Say MediaWe partner with Say Media to deliver ad campaigns on our sites. (Privacy Policy)
Remarketing PixelsWe may use remarketing pixels from advertising networks such as Google AdWords, Bing Ads, and Facebook in order to advertise the HubPages Service to people that have visited our sites.
Conversion Tracking PixelsWe may use conversion tracking pixels from advertising networks such as Google AdWords, Bing Ads, and Facebook in order to identify when an advertisement has successfully resulted in the desired action, such as signing up for the HubPages Service or publishing an article on the HubPages Service.
Statistics
Author Google AnalyticsThis is used to provide traffic data and reports to the authors of articles on the HubPages Service. (Privacy Policy)
ComscoreComScore is a media measurement and analytics company providing marketing data and analytics to enterprises, media and advertising agencies, and publishers. Non-consent will result in ComScore only processing obfuscated personal data. (Privacy Policy)
Amazon Tracking PixelSome articles display amazon products as part of the Amazon Affiliate program, this pixel provides traffic statistics for those products (Privacy Policy)
ClickscoThis is a data management platform studying reader behavior (Privacy Policy)